Euclid's Theorem on the Infinitude of Prime Numbers

Prime numbers are infinite because for any given prime number P, there always exists a larger prime.

To prove that there are infinitely many prime numbers, Euclid constructs a new number that cannot be divisible by any existing prime numbers, leading to the conclusion that new prime numbers must exist.

The Proof

Euclid's key idea is to assume that a prime number \( P \) is the largest of all.

He calculates the product of all prime numbers up to \( P \) and adds 1:

$$ n = (2 \times 3 \times 5 \times... \times P)+1 $$

This new number \( n \) is not divisible by any of the primes up to \( P \) because it always leaves a remainder of 1.

Moreover, since we added 1, we know that \( n \) is greater than \( P \):

$$ n > P $$

At this point, there are two possibilities:

  • If \( n \) is a prime number, then \( P \) is not the largest prime.
  • If \( n \) is composite, it must have at least one prime factor. Since we already established that \( n \) is not divisible by any of the primes up to \( P \), there must be another prime \( P' \) greater than \( P \). This contradicts our assumption that \( P \) was the largest prime.

In both cases, our initial assumption is proven false: \( P \) is not the largest prime.

Therefore, the opposite must be true: for any given prime \( P \), there always exists a larger prime.

From this, we conclude that prime numbers are infinite.

Note: In some versions of Euclid's proof, 1 is added, while in others, 1 is subtracted. The result remains the same. In both cases, divisibility by all primes up to \( P \) is broken, ensuring that the resulting number \( n \) is not divisible by any of them.

A Practical Example

Let's assume, for the sake of argument, that 5 is the largest prime number.

The prime numbers up to 5 are: \( 2, 3, 5 \). We compute their product and add 1:

$$ n = (2 \times 3 \times 5) + 1 = 30 + 1 = 31 $$

The number \( n = 31 \) is not divisible by any of the primes up to 5, as division always leaves a remainder of 1.

  • 31 is not divisible by 2, since \( 31 \div 2 = 15 \) with a remainder of 1.
  • 31 is not divisible by 3, since \( 31 \div 3 = 10 \) with a remainder of 1.
  • 31 is not divisible by 5, since \( 31 \div 5 = 6 \) with a remainder of 1.

Since 31 is not divisible by any of the primes up to 5, there are two possible conclusions:

  • If \( n = 31 \) is prime, then \( P = 5 \) is not the largest prime.
  • If \( n = 31 \) is not a prime, then it must be divisible by some other prime. Since \( n \) is not divisible by any of the primes up to \( P \), there must exist another prime \( P' > P \).

In both cases, we have shown that \( P = 5 \) is not the largest prime.

Note: In this case, \( n \) is itself a prime number. However, even if it were not, the proof would still demonstrate the existence of a prime greater than \( P \). For example, with \( P = 13 \), we get:

$$ n = (2 \times 3 \times 5 \times 7 \times 11 \times 13) + 1 = 30031 $$

The number \( n = 30031 \) is not prime, but it is divisible by \( P' = 59 \), which is greater than \( P = 13 \). So even in this case, there exists a prime larger than \( P \).

An Alternative Proof

Let's assume we have three prime numbers \( a, b, c \) and aim to prove the existence of a fourth prime.

$$ a, b, c \in P $$

We construct a new number \( d \):

$$ d = abc + 1 $$

If \( d \) is a prime number, then we have proven the theorem:

$$ d \in P $$

If \( d \) is not a prime, then there must exist some prime \( d' \) that divides \( abc \):

$$ d \notin P \rightarrow d' | abc $$

In this case:

  • If \( d' \) is different from \( a, b, c \), then we have found a new prime, proving the theorem.
    $$ d' \ne (a \land b \land c ) $$
  • If \( d' \) is equal to one of the primes \( a, b, c \), then it should also divide the difference between \( abc \) and \( abc+1 \), which is 1. However, this is impossible.
    $$ d' = ( a \lor b \lor c ) \rightarrow \:\: contradiction $$

Therefore, if \( d' \) is a prime, it must be different from \( a, b, c \), proving the existence of another prime.

Note: This confirms that the sequence of prime numbers is infinite. The same theorem can be generalized by considering \( n \) prime numbers where

$$ d = p_1 + ... + p_n + 1 $$

and proving the existence of an additional prime \( p_{n+1} \).

 

 
 

Please feel free to point out any errors or typos, or share suggestions to improve these notes. English isn't my first language, so if you notice any mistakes, let me know, and I'll be sure to fix them.

FacebookTwitterLinkedinLinkedin
knowledge base

Prime Numbers

FAQ